Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2011
My intention is to discuss briefly several elements of the connection between liberal democracy and religion. This topic is decisive in much of Richard Neuhaus' work. Conserving liberty is a central task today, and religion's place in this task important, although controversial. The orientation of my paper is toward this political or ethical issue, not toward faith as such. One should recognize, however, that from some secular standpoints the unlikelihood, improbability, or lack of evidence for revelation shapes from the start the seriousness with which one addresses the connection between religion and politics. From these standpoints, the moral height and strength of the Jewish and Christian revelations is not as such evidence of their truth. The fact that Farabi, Maimonides, Aquinas, Hobbes, Locke, Kant, and Hegel -and in their own way Plato and Aristotle -considered the issue of the connection between thought and faith does not show its intellectual power. We and they grapple with a problem that there is no special intellectual reason to deal with earnestly -as distinguished from historical or political reasons. The evidence for revelation is not greater than that of other possibilities one would not dream of taking seriously. Similar (although opposed) assurance may also govern those convinced by faith. It is sometimes said that judgments about the importance or superiority of reason cannot escape from an original leap of faith not different in principle from faith as we ordinarily understand it. The choice to follow along reason's path must at first be irrational, or not demonstrated. One begins by assuming a superiority of reason that one cannot prove. Yet, this argument apparently does not lead those who doubt the evidence and authority of pious faith to take its claim more seriously. One reason is that, however reason begins, its journey can always remain open to
By the second half of the eleventh century, in the Christian West, the theological doctrine of St. Anslem sought to re-establish the place of reason within the domain of faith. Anselm arrived at a possible re-enactment of this relation under the condition regulated by the principle fides quaerens intellectum -faith seeking reason. This paper is an attempt to explore not only the possible implications of this principle but to understand the internal logic which constitutes it and holds it together. It is the contention of this paper that this regulative principle (fides quaerens intellectum) could complete such a process of logically constituting itself through a violent forcing of thought which gathered and maintained within itself an anomy. This internal paradox produced a logical excess which at one hand threatened constantly to expose a crisis, inhabiting the very centre of the theological system it sought to build, but on the other hand it also became the very ground on which such a system constituted itself. To that extent this paper would try to understand the metaphysical forcing of this moment of crisis back into the theological system it sought to express and normalize at the same time.
Leo Strauss and His Catholic Readers
This article was published in Mosaic (Winter, 2008), pp. 2-5. It explores the West's vulnerability to irrationalism following its ironic revolt against reason in the wake of the Age of Reason's revolt against faith -- an irony briefly touched upon in Albert Camus' *The Rebel*. This turns on its head the usual conceit that it was the Enlightenment that saved us from the authoritarian irrationalism of the Middle Ages. The irony, again, is that nearly the opposite is true, and as Peter Kreeft points out, Medieval philosophers were rational to a fault, while modern philosophies since the Enlightenment have attacked reason in dozens of ways and dogmatically exalted instead the authority of ideology, politics, the passions, or power, or pragmatism, or positivism, or Deconstructionism, or Marxism, or Freudianism, or Romanticism, or Existentialism, so that nearly the whole of Western philosophy since the Enlightenment has been a sustained attack on reason. Yet another irony is that a representative of the historic bastions of authoritarian dogmatism, Pope John Paul II, should be seen in this context as coming to the defense not of blind faith, but of reason, in his encyclical *Fides et Ratio*, in which he shows how "faith becomes the certain and persuasive advocate of reason."
"The courage to engage the whole breadth of reason, and not the denial of its grandeur - this is the program with which a theology grounded in Biblical faith enters into the debates of our time" (Benedict XVI) This study begins with a detailed historical reconstruction of the relationship between faith and reason from the particular point of view of the Catholic Magisterium. It then considers how Catholic thought has dealt with this question. In reconsidering the relationship between faith and reason, it suggests a key understanding based on the concept of truth as "meaning"; in this way reason is conceived as a "sought meaning" and faith as a "given meaning." This idea, united with the necessary presupposition of Truth as a horizon of both Reason and Faith, suggests new ways for a fruitful dialogue between faith and reason in the postmodern age - an age in which a reductive concept of reason and an inadequate idea of faith seem to prevail.
Article , 2025
Faith and reason are two fundamental concepts that have shaped human thought, belief systems, and our understanding of existence. Faith is often defined as a belief in something that may not be provable through empirical evidence or rational means. At the same time, reason is the cognitive process through which individuals draw logical conclusions based on available data and methodologies. The interplay between faith and reason has been a subject of intense philosophical inquiry, particularly regarding how these two forms of understanding coexist, conflict, or complement each other in the pursuit of truth and knowledge. Historically, various thinkers have proposed different models to explain the relationship between faith and reason. Some argue for a conflict model, suggesting that when faith and reason address the same questions, they often yield contradictory answers. Conversely, others advocate for an incompatibilist model, positing that faith and reason pertain to distinct realms-faith addressing spiritual truths and reason focusing on empirical realities and therefore reason as the ultimate authority 1. The weak compatibilist model suggests a dialogue between the two, allowing for a harmonious coexistence where both can inform one another without undermining their unique contributions 2. Finally, the strong compatibilist model asserts that faith can be supported by rational arguments, as seen in natural theology. This essay will explore these models in depth, examining key arguments surrounding the authority of faith and reason, their interrelationship, and the implications for human belief systems. By analyzing historical perspectives and contemporary interpretations, we aim to illuminate how faith and reason together shape our understanding of reality. II. Historical Perspective on Faith and Reason The historical relationship between faith and reason has evolved significantly through various philosophical and theological perspectives. Initially, in the early Christian context, thinkers like Tertullian emphasized a conflict model, suggesting that faith transcends reason, famously stating 1 "Faith and Reason," Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2 "Reason and Faith: A Conflict through the History of Philosophy," ResearchGate.
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 2016
We find in contemporary culture starkly contrasting estimates of the value of faith. On the one hand, for many people, faith is a virtue or positive human value, something associated with understanding, hope, and love, something to be inculcated, maintained, and cherished. On the other hand, for many people, faith is a vice, something associated with dogmatism, arrogance, and close-mindedness, something to be avoided at all costs. The papers included in this special (double) issue on approaches to faith explore questions about faith in a variety of settings through a diverse range of examples, both secular and religious. The attempt to deepen our understanding of faith in the context of ordinary human relationships (e.g., between parents and children, friends, generals and their armies, business partners, citizens and the state), a commitment to ideals, or the pursuit of significant goals is clearly of general philosophical interest, as is the examination of potential connections between faith and topics such as trust or reliance. Discussion of the specific role that faith plays in religious contexts is also a matter of general social concern. Interest in religious faith, at least in the English-speaking world, has been amplified in recent years, not least in response to ongoing acts of religiously motivated violence such as the terrorist attacks in New York City and Washington, D.C. on September 11, 2001. The question ''Would the world be better off without
Utilitas, 1999
Dialogues between Faith and Reason, 2011
Philosophy & Rhetoric , 2014
Reason, religion, and public culture have been of significant interest recently, with critics reevaluating modernity’s conception of secularism and calling for a “post secular” public discourse. Simultaneously, one sees rising religious fundamentalisms and a growing style of antirationalism in public debate. These conditions make a reconceptualization of public reason necessary. The main goals of this article are to establish agnostic public reason as the conceptual guide and normative ethic for public debate in liberal democracies by considering the secular/religious reason boundary explicitly and to argue that this ethic of public reason requires a commitment to reason giving and a particular epistemic attitude but that it does not, nor should it, take precedence over first-order judgments. An ethics of citizenship based on the process of reason giving with the appropriate epistemic stance might be one step toward rectifying the problem of an increasing separation between enclave publics, even if, by design, it cannot solve fundamental disagreement.
This article attempts to present a typology for evaluating religious truth claims in light of epistemological and metaphysical categories. Beginning with a distinction between "strong" and "weak" epistemological and metaphysical categories, it argues that a strong metaphysical set of beliefs need not be rooted in strong epistemological claims in order to be valid. Rather, it is possible to ground a "strong" set of metaphysical assertions within a "weak" epistemological framework, which, within its own framework, may be viewed to be presumptively true. Such a position, the article concludes, has the potential to provide a valid grounding for religious beliefs while allowing room for discourse across belief systems in a pluralistic society.
The Court of Reason, 2022
In this paper, I unpack Kant’s oft-cited and overstated declaration, “I had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith,” in relation to his account of rational faith in the “Orientation” essay and his defense of freedom in the final section of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. In the “Orientation” essay, Kant translates faith in God into a rationally acceptable assumption, an orienting belief. This allows us to understand how in the Groundwork, at the “extreme boundary” of practical philosophy, Kant transforms freedom itself into a matter of faith, i.e., a necessary presupposition and orienting idea. Faith, thus altered, becomes a key weapon in Kant’s critical arsenal as he mounts a full-scale defense of freedom against the moral skeptic.
2015
Historically, the scientific dynamism of the classical Islamic society stands as a challenge to the notion that religion and science are inherently approved.
2009
The public/private split lies at the heart of classical liberalism.1 One of its main tenets is that religion be confined to the private sphere so that the sphere of public reason can proceed peacefully. However, recent developments in philosophical conceptions of reason challenge the supposed neutrality of the public sphere and thereby call into question the viability of the public- private split. These consequences cry out for a re-examination of the proper roles of reason and religion in a re-conceived sphere of ‘public’ reason. In this paper, I will begin by arguing for the notion of presuppositional reason, with support from Dooyeweerd, Derrida, and Quine (Section I). Having made my case for the presuppositional nature of reason, I will then argue that it requires some set of beliefs at its core that function ‘religiously’, thereby challenging the supposed neutrality of the secular state (Section II). Without the neutrality of the secular state, the divisions between church and state and private and public that this neutrality makes possible are called into question. In the next section, then, I will suggest a new, testimonial function of reason and religion that can operate in a re- conceived notion of the ‘public’ sphere that gets beyond the myth of neutrality (Section III). Finally, I will end by showing how the testimonial differs from Habermas’ liberal conception of the role of self-reflexive religion in the public sphere, and how the position I put forward in this paper is therefore distinct from liberalism (Section IV).
A novel account of the rationality of religious belief is offered, called quasi- fideism. According to this proposal, we are neither to think of religious belief as completely immune to rational evaluation nor are we to deny that it involves fundamental commitments which are arational. Moreover, a parity argument is presented to the effect that religious belief is no different from ordinary rational belief in presupposing such fundamental arational commitments. This proposal is shown to be rooted in Wittgenstein’s remarks on hinge commitments in On Certainty, remarks which it is claimed were in turn influenced by John Henry Newman’s treatment of the rationality of religious belief in An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent.
The Cambridge Companion to Religious Epistemology , 2022
Faith in God conflicts with reason—or so we’re told. We focus on two arguments for this conclusion. After evaluating three criticisms of them, we identify an assumption they share, namely that faith in God requires belief that God exists. Whether the assumption is true depends on what faith is. We sketch a theory of faith that allows for both faith in God without belief that God exists, and faith in God while in belief-cancelling doubt God’s existence. We then argue that our theory, unlike the theory of Thomas Aquinas, makes sense of four central items of faith-data: (i) pístis in the Synoptics, (ii) ʾemunāh in the Hebrew scriptures, (iii) exemplars of faith in God, including Abraham, Jesus, and Mother Teresa, and (iv) the widespread experience of people of faith today. We close by assessing revisions of the two arguments we began with, revisions that align with our theory of faith, and find them dubious, at best.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.