Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2018, Educational Philosophy and Theory
https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2018.1493681…
12 pages
1 file
The struggle to become lucid is at the heart of The Myth of Sisyphus. To understand the absurd is to understand that the fit between our conception of the world and the world itself is fraught with uncertainty; lucidity is the elucidation of the absurd. To be lucid is to revolt against the type of certainty that leads to suffering; to revolt against philosophical suicide. Camus teaches us the intellectual humility that stays hands; there is no reasoning that justifies suffering. If it is granted that the ability to recognise and respond to our own and others suffering is an important part of being human, and the task of education is to develop humans, then lucidity, in so far as it holds promise for the development of such an ability, has the potential to contribute positively to education. The one major objective of education will no longer be to produce primarily a rational man or social animal; it will no longer be, as the Educational Policies Commission would have it, to discover the values inherent in rationality; rather, if we take our cue from Camus, education will have a new primary objective: to produce the moral individual-moral because, in the face of the absurd, he lucidly lives the philosophy of limits. (p. 127)
2018
Camus takes suicide to be the most important of all philosophical questions. It is a bold starting point, one that has received much attention. Camus was, however, concerned with two types of suicide: physical and philosophical. I concentrate on the latter without neglecting the former, to bring out the relationship between them, and the implications this relationship holds for education; namely, the promise of the creation of lucid individuals.
Zanetti, L. “Leaving Our Grasping Ego Behind”. Learning from Suffering in the Community of Philosophical Inquiry, in The Community of Philosophical Enquiry as Citizenship Education: Global Perspectives on Talking Democracy into Action, ed. by J. Frostenzerr, F. Demissie, V. Boontinand, Routledge., 2024
Drawing insights from Buddhism and Stoicism, in this paper I shall provide a sketch of a theory of suffering according to which suffering depends on our desires that reality be in a certain way and the belief that reality differs from how we desire it to be. Then I shall argue for two further claims: that most of our desires, in turn, depend on our beliefs; that most of our beliefs, in turn, depend on our philosophical beliefs. In this way I shall argue that most of our suffering depends on our philosophical beliefs. This view has far-reaching educational implications. In this paper, I shall explore some of these implications for moral and civic education in the context of the pedagogy of the Community of Inquiry elaborated by Matthew Lipman, Ann Sharp, and colleagues within the educational movement of Philosophy for Children. By paying attention to our suffering in dialogue, we can learn which desires and beliefs make us suffer, and through dialogic inquiry we can explore whether our desires and beliefs are rational and, if not, we can eventually learn through practice and inquiry to relax their hold on us, which is crucial for both moral and civic growth.
Theoria, Beograd, 2008
This paper tries to extricate philosophical education from the restrictions of social and school systems and to commend some independent and subversive views. This is to be accomplished through a conceptual dissection of the term 'education'. On the one hand, there is education seen as transmitter of the tradition, where to be educated is seen as being able to fit into an established community. There is also another education to which the authority of tradition is a permanent target of resistance, always trying to undermine any educational uniformity. This second history of education, genuinely philosophical, is radically opposed to the history of institutionalized mass-education. However, intention of this paper is not to proclaim this as an 'alternative' model, or to build it up as a new mythology. On the contrary, it is being written as a history of continuous subversion. Viewed from this vantage point, autonomous philosophical education is not a subsystem of a so...
Filozofija i drustvo, 2006
This paper tries to extricate philosophical education from the restrictions of social and school systems and to commend some independent and subversive views. This is to be accomplished through a conceptual dissection of the term 'education'. On the one hand, there is education seen as transmitter of the tradition, where to be educated is seen as being able to fit into an established community. There is also another education to which the authority of tradition is a permanent target of resistance, always trying to undermine any educational uniformity. This second history of education, genuinely philosophical, is radically opposed to the history of institutionalized mass-education. However, intention of this paper is not to proclaim this as an "alternative" model, or to build it up as a new mythology. On the contrary, it is being written as a history of continuous subversion. Viewed from this vantage point, autonomous philosophical education is not a subsystem of a social system. This education has itself as a measurement, and always resists the wider community (the environment) that has accidentally befallen it. Its honor is exactly in this attitude of resistance, in being watchful against any conscription and integration. Understood in this manner, philosophical education is not a useful "implemented" function of society, but is rather its dysfunction.
Philosophy of Education …, 2009
Last spring, I had one of my best educational experiences ever: I co-taught with Maxine Greene-and so, co-learnt with the students-a course on existentialism and education. We spent several weeks on Sartre's Being and Nothingness, a book I had not read since my teens. I was astonished and captivated anew by Sartre's journey to the heart of la condition humaine, and found myself wondering about existentialism's absurd end. How did I, following the intellectual culture I grew up with, lose interest in making sense of my mortality? Isn't it strange that, outside of a few stalwarts like Maxine, the spirit of existentialism so completely vanished, like yesterday's nouvelle vague? Imagine, then, my great pleasure, and relief, when I discovered what a Manhattan provincial I am, that anguished freedom was alive and writing in Normal, Illinois. Dying to Teach: The Educator's Search for Immortality challenges educators to respond to two questions. Shouldn't we affirm education as a humanistic calling, by understanding it as a response to our human, mortal condition? And if so, then what difference would that affirmation make to the practice of teaching? In this brief commentary, I shall support Prof. David Blacker's claim that we ought to root education in an acknowledgment of the mortality that both individualizes and gathers us together. Proceeding from that central point of agreement, I shall also try to explain, however, some of my reservations regarding his advice to teachers. I worry that the only students who could be fully engaged by David's education in immortality, and who could be truly at home there, would be the eternal undead. For those who expect to stay in their coffins, on the other hand, this kind of teaching could represent what Sartre calls distraction. I would like to respectfully suggest that David's project to humanize teaching might be aided by a more focused attack on such distracting forces in our lives, and on the fear that makes us vulnerable to them. Modern Western culture has increasingly distanced itself from death. Building on the historical work of Philippe Aries, David notes that, "Death becomes something essentially alien to ourselves, our true selves, our eternal souls. We shove death away in so many ways (p. 21)." But of course, this distancing is problematic, because our mortality is inescapably closer to us than any putative truths beyond. David agrees with Heidegger that our lives are essentially marked by constant anxiety about our precarious and transient being. When Heidegger states that we are ontically distinctive in that we are ontological, he means that one of the observable characteristics of human beings-and our most unique feature-is that our very existence is always at issue for us. Not that we are always conscious that it is; this awareness of our own contingency, our own mortality, is not typically explicit. But it is nonetheless there, somewhere, at some level (p. 28).
Education and Thinking in Continental Philosophy: Thinking against the Current in Adorno, Arendt, Deleuze, Derrida and Rancière, 2020
This chapter aims at reconstructing Derrida's concept of thinking and analyzing its relations to education. The starting point is "Cogito and the History of Madness", where Derrida argues against Foucault's reading of Descartes’ reference to madness in the first chapter of his Meditations. While Foucault claims that Descartes constitutes a dichotomous opposition between thought and madness, Derrida shows that madness finds its way into the Cartesian cogito and into thought itself. This debate, I argue, has interesting educational implications: Derrida presents both Foucault and Descartes as teachers who not only provide their students with knowledge, but also leave them with the madness required to break discursive boundaries and think for themselves. Next, I broaden the perspective and show that Derrida understands thinking, like every system of signification, as a kind of writing – the thinking subject is in fact a writing subject who does not fully master the meanings of her thoughts. Finally, I turn to Derrida's writings on education: I discuss his call to make room in schools for thinking against the predominant "philosophy of the state", and analyze his claim that the university should "blink", namely think of the conditions making thinking possible within its walls.
Nietzsche on Time and History, ed. Manuel Dries (Walter de Gruyter, 2008)
It is often claimed that medieval Jewish philosophy is unashamedly elitist. In contrast to Socrates who had been content to discuss philosophy with whomever he met, both freemen and slaves, the medieval philosophers shunned contact with the ignorant multitude. The Jewish philosopher Moses Maimonides (d. 1204) is often seen as personifying this trend. According to him, human beings achieve salvation in accordance with the measure in which they succeed in channeling the emanation of the divine intellect, an activity which requires considerable intellectual ability and expertise. "As for the ignorant and disobedient, " he says, their state is despicable proportionately to the lack of this emanation, and they have been relegated to the rank of the individuals of all other species of animals: 'He is like the beasts that speak not. ' 2 For this reason, it is a light thing to kill them, and has been even enjoined because of its utility. 3 1 This paper is dedicated to Harry Fox to whom I am very grateful for having initiated me in the mysteries of the Guide of the Perplexed during my senior year of college. His close-readings of the Guide have continued to influence the way I read the works of Maimonides and his successors. I would also like to thank James Robinson and my father, Milton Verskin, for having commented upon previous versions of this paper.
The Pluralist, 2009
SATS, 2023
The introduction provides a brief conspectus of why philosophers have such a wide range of educational responsibilities, too many of which are too often neglected.
Educational Philosophy and Theory
Inspired by Camus' portrayal of Sisyphus, this essay examines the act of teaching as an absurd profession, one that faces numerous obstacles and challenges and continually falls short of its intended goals. I begin my analysis by demonstrating that Camus' understanding of the absurd was heavily influenced by Nietzsche's conception of nihilism. I argue that for Camus the sense of absurdity comes from the conflict between humans' longing for order and meaning and the disorder and meaninglessness that we experience in our daily lives. Next, I show that Camus' understanding of absurdity can help us make sense of the recent wave of educational reform. More fundamentally, I argue that that the existential conditions of schooling that many teachers have to negotiate daily are themselves absurd in Camus' sense of the term. In the last part of this article, I take a close look at how a number of teachers are attempting to resist and even rebel against the new educational mandates.
When one travels around the world, one notices to what an extraordinary degree human nature is the same, whether in India or America, in Europe or Australia. This is especially true in colleges and universities. We are turning out, as if through a mould, a type of human being whose chief interest is to find security, to become somebody important, or to have a good time with as little thought as possible.
Avi Mintz (2008) has recently argued that Anglo-American educators have a tendency to alleviate student suffering in the classroom. According to Mintz, this tendency can be detrimental because certain kinds of suffering actually enhance student learning. While Mintz compellingly describes the effects of educator’s desires to alleviate suffering in students, he does not examine one of the roots of the desire: the feeling of compassion or pity (used as synonyms here). Compassion leads many teachers to unreflectively alleviate student struggles. While there are certainly times when compassion is necessary to help students learn, there are other times when it must be overcome. Compassion in the classroom is a two-edged sword that must be carefully employed; and yet it is often assumed that it is an unequivocal good that ought to trump all other impulses. In this article I hope to raise awareness concerning the promises and pitfalls of compassion in education by examining the theories of two historical figures who famously emphasised compassion in their philosophical writings: Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Friedrich Nietzsche. Rousseau and Nietzsche argue that compassion is a powerful educational force but that it must be properly employed. For Rousseau and Nietzsche, compassion is necessary to develop self-mastery in human beings—the ultimate goal of education—but it is a compassion that must hurt in order to help. My hope is that Rousseau’s and Nietzsche’s ideas on compassion will encourage thoughtful reflection on the uses and abuses of compassion in education.
While a great deal has been written on Plato's Lysis in philosophy and philology journals over the last thirty years, nothing has been published on Lysis in the major Anglo-American philosophy of education journals during that time. Nevertheless, this dialogue deserves attention from educators. In this essay, Mark Jonas argues that Lysis can serve as a model for educators who want to move their students beyond mere aporia, but also do not want to dictate answers to students. Although the dialogue ends in Socrates's affirmation of aporia, his affirmation is actually meant to persuade his interlocutors to reflect on an epiphany they had previously experienced. In what follows, Jonas offers a close reading of relevant passages of Lysis, demonstrating the way that Socrates leads his interlocutors to an epiphany without forcing his answers upon them.
This article attempts to identify certain shortcomings in analytic philosophy as practised today. First, it identifies a disconnect between the darker aspects of the human condition and philosophers' inability to engage with them. Second, it locates this inability in a certain logic of detachment, explored by Peter Strawson. Third, it points out problems with Strawson's analysis, which it then tries to overcome, using Constantin Noica's account of the Platonising attitude philosophers are perennially tempted by-one of several ways in which humans try to overcome their fallen condition. This is contrasted with Thomas Nagel's valuable but still deficient discussion of the "cosmic question". This brings us, finally, to a reconsideration of an older tradition in philosophy, which focused more explicitly on human fallenness. Petrarch's Secretum meum is used as an example to show that while the failure of analytic philosophers has deep existential roots, it is not commendable. Philosophers must learn, again, to reflect on the darkness of the human soul-their own darkness.
Studies in Philosophy and Education, 2012
Nowadays there is a renewed interest in philosophy as art-of-living. Several prominent authors have pointed out the return of the notion of the good life in philosophy, particularly understood as a form of normative ethics. Questions such as: how should I live have been taken up as a resistance against the dominances of a neo-liberal discourse in all areas of life. This paper is concerned with this renewed interest in philosophy as art-ofliving and the form of education that supports this. The main idea is that the commitment from which we live is a subject of change. This way, art-of-living comprises the possibility and the effort to lead on's life in a reflective way, and not to let it simply go by. Historically this has been connected to the process of becoming educated. In this paper I will take a closer look at this renewed interest in philosophy as the art-of-living by contrasting two different readings of philosophy as the art-of-living. One that is inspired by Oscar Brenifier and one that is inspired by the late Foucault.
In this essay I begin with remarks made by Bernard Williams that there are two main motives for philosophy, curiosity and salvation, and that he is not ‘into salvation’. I seek to make the case for the claim that philosophy, at its best, should aim at a kind of 'salvation’. In the first section, I discuss the problematic character of the world that philosophy should aim to address as a matter of seeking a kind of salvation. I identify this as the problem of ‘cosmodicy’, i.e., the problem of how to justify life in the world as meaningful and worthwhile in the face of extensive evil, suffering, disorder, and the like. In the second section, I discuss how Williams’s claim not to be ‘into salvation’ is not entirely accurate. Although he rejects a certain ‘grand’ traditional picture of salvation, he still seeks a more minimal kind insofar as he addresses the problem of cosmodicy. This comes through in his advocacy of ‘humane’ philosophy and in his attempt to support the values that arise for us from within our historically contingent forms of life. I argue here that Williams is wrong to reject the human concern for a larger cosmic significance. In the final section, I discuss two secular attempts to address the issue of cosmic significance: viz., those of Thomas Nagel and Paolo Costa. I also briefly consider here what a theistic perspective has to offer. I conclude by suggesting that if I am right that philosophy, at is best, should aim at a kind of salvation, then this means that the philosophy of religion should have a central place in any philosophy curriculum.
Studies in Philosophy of Education , 2022
Greek literature prior to Plato featured two conceptions of education. Learning takes place when people encounter “teacher-guides”—educators, mentors, and advisors. But education also occurs outside of a pedagogical relationship between learner and teacher-guide: people learn through painful experience. In composing his dramatic dialogues, Plato appropriated these two conceptions of education, refashioning and fusing them to present a new philosophical conception of learning: Plato’s Socrates is a teacher-guide who causes his interlocutors to learn through suffering. Socrates, however, is not presented straightforwardly as a pedagogical success story. Socrates’ failures are, paradoxically, part of what makes him an ideal literary model for a philosophical teacher-guide. Plato requires his readers to question why Socrates’ interlocutors fail to be converted to philosophers.
Education Sciences
This is a collection of articles preoccupied with the future of education [...]
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.